Five Thousand B.C. and Other Philosophical Fantasies by Raymond M. Smullyan

By Raymond M. Smullyan

Five Thousand B.C. and different Philosophical Fantasies via Raymond Smullyan is a set of paradoxes, dialogues, difficulties, and essays exploring philosophical principles. This interesting ebook will problem your figuring out of fact, fact, morality, life, and death.

Raymond Smullyan is a philosopher, mathematician, and thinker and is the writer of books together with The Tao Is Silent, What Is the identify of This Book?, To Mock a Mockinbird and others.

Show description

Read Online or Download Five Thousand B.C. and Other Philosophical Fantasies PDF

Similar philosophy books

Œuvres, tome 1 (La Pochothèque)

Bergson a connu une carrière à l. a. fois brillante et traditionnelle : ancien élève de l’École normale supérieure, agrégé de philosophie, il devient professeur de lycée et soutient sa thèse, Essai sur les données immédiates de los angeles moral sense, en 1889.

Scienza nuova (BUR Classici)

Mentre l’Europa è percorsa dai primi rivoli dell’Illuminismo, Vico lavora incessantemente alla redazione della Scienza nuova: analizzando il linguaggio, i miti, le leggi, cerca un sistema di conoscenza globale che permetta di indagare il rapporto tra l’uomo e il proprio passato.

The Discovery of the Mind in Greek Philosophy and Literature

German classicist's enormous examine of the origins of ecu suggestion in Greek literature and philosophy. remarkable, generally influential. contains "Homer's View of Man," "The Olympian Gods," "The upward thrust of the person within the Early Greek Lyric," "Pindar's Hymn to Zeus," "Myth and truth in Greek Tragedy," and "Aristophanes and Aesthetic feedback.

Additional resources for Five Thousand B.C. and Other Philosophical Fantasies

Example text

It cannot consist simply in reality’s impressing itself on our minds, for in order for this to result in knowledge of reality, there would have to be something about us which made us appropriately receptive to it: our minds would have to be capable of transforming the impress of reality into a representation of it. That is, we would have to be already immanently related to reality. Nor does it help to reverse the story and conceive our contact with reality as the result of our own activity, since in order for our minds to reach out and read off the features of reality, we would have to know how to locate and read it - and again this condition could not be fulfilled unless reality were already an immanent object for us.

In my dissertation I was content to explain the nature of intellectual representations in a merely negative way, namely, to state that they were not modifications of the soul brought about -28- by the object. However, I silently passed over the further question of how a representation that refers to an object without being in any way affected by it can be possible. I had said: The sensuous representations present things as they appear, the intellectual presentations present them as they are. But by what means are these things given to us, if not by the way in which they affect us?

Kant does not intend to merely assume the truth of transcendental idealism at the outset and trace its consequences. Recognising that something positive must be done to establish his metaphysic, Kant describes it as the ‘main purpose’ of the Critique, not merely to articulate, but to prove the doctrine of transcendental idealism (Bxxii). Two attempted proofs are presented: an ‘apodictic’ proof in the Transcendental Aesthetic and Transcendental Analytic, concerned with space and time and the concepts of the understanding (Bxxii[n]); and an ‘indirect’ proof in the Antinomy of Pure Reason, according to which the assumption that the objects of knowledge are things in themselves leads unavoidably to contradictions (Bxx).

Download PDF sample

Rated 4.50 of 5 – based on 26 votes